![]() I read this earlier on in the year (January or February 2022) and put off writing a book summary until now. The book summary is not as detailed as what I hoped to write. Climate Leviathan is a great work of political theory (I have absolutely no formal training in political science or political philosophy—my assessment should not be taken as authoritative) that attempts to sketch out how the concept of the political will change due to the ongoing pressures of the climate crisis. In Wainwright and Mann’s view, the most likely future is the Climate Leviathan, which marks a continuation of capitalist social relations and planetary sovereignty, justified as a “state of exception” by global capitalist elites to preserve life on Earth. This is not Wainwright and Mann’s preferred future: by writing this book, they also attempt to liberate alternative ways of thinking: “If good climate data and models were all that were needed to address climate change, we would have seen a political response in the 1980s. Our challenge is closer to a crisis of imagination and ideology; people do not change their conception of the world just because they are presented with new data…” (p. 7). Wainwright and Mann sketch out four political possibilities by taking two dichotomous conditions. The first condition asks whether future forms will be capitalist or non-capitalist and the second condition asks whether there will be a planetary sovereignty with decision making authority. From these two conditions, four “ideal type” political possibilities emerge: these are hegemonic blocs with their own class and ideological bases. There is the capitalist Climate Leviathan that strives for planetary sovereignty; Climate Mao, which is a non-capitalist planetary sovereign; Climate Behemoth, capitalist and anti-planetary sovereignty; and the inchoate Climate X, which is non-capitalist and against planetary sovereignty. The challenge of climate change is so great that we cannot assume the continuation of capitalist liberal democracies as the dominant political form. These four forms will struggle to frame political responses to climate change, shaping the world along these struggles. I provide a further (but still brief) description of each form. Climate Leviathan is the realization of a planetary sovereign that “is a regulatory authority armed with democratic legitimacy, binding technical authority on scientific issues, and panopticon-like capacity to monitor the vital granular elements of our emerging world” (p. 30)—Wainwright and Mann point to the UN COP meetings as an early iteration. Bounded, nation-state-based regulatory regimes are unable to meet the challenge of climate change. Climate Leviathan represents an international regime, but one that is “the construction of a nominally ‘global’ frame that is in fact a political and geographical extension of the rule of the extant hegemonic blog: the capitalist global North” (p. 31). Wainwright and Mann point out that the capitalist foundations of Climate Leviathan may prevent its emergence, given that the inequalities generated by capitalism lead to difficulties with trans-class and transnational cooperation. Climate Behemoth is a reactionary movement to the climate crisis. It is often marked by climate change denial and is opposed to international intrusions into domestic politics (and by extension, it is opposed to Climate Leviathan). It has so far expressed itself in ethnonationalist and reactionary populist movements (e.g., Modi, Trump, Brexit) led by neoliberal elites and disenfranchised groups who feel threatened by climate action (e.g., Koch brothers and workers in the gas and oil sector). Like Climate Leviathan, Climate Mao is also based on a planetary sovereign, but one that “wields this power against capital” (p. 38). In contrast to Climate Leviathan’s “lop-sided, elite-based, liberal proceduralism” (p. 39), which is moving us too slowly to make the systemic changes necessary to address climate change, Climate Mao has the power to make rapid state-led transformations to society. Wainwright and Mann think that Climate Mao is a uniquely Asian path given certain historical and current conditions: “massive and marginalized peasantries and proletariats, historical experience and revolutionary ideology, and powerful states governing large economies” (p. 41), along with the disproportionate effects of climate change in Asia (e.g. the floods in Pakistan earlier this year). Finally, Climate X is the future in formation by the climate justice movement; it is a non-sovereign alternative to Climate Leviathan that transcends capitalism, motivated by the guiding principles of equality, inclusion and dignity of all, and solidarity of many worlds. An ever-inchoate formation, it is determined not by universal claims to a common “we,” but by local conditions, histories, experiences; it is Wainwright and Mann’s hopeful future for the troubled world to come.
0 Comments
![]() Mazzucato’s approachable Mission Economy attempts to rethink and reform capitalism, presenting an alternative to its current (perhaps on the sunset) neoliberal orientation. This new capitalism sees the public sector take back its role as a key partner and shaper of the economy. Our current political-economic structures are unable to address the global problems facing the world today, most important of which are problems related to the environment. She identifies four sources of our dysfunctional capitalism.
Given the responsibility of dominant economic frameworks on our troubled status quo, Mazzucato looks to dispel erroneous myths about the government, naming five myths in particular.
In place of these myths, Mazzucato writes that value is the cumulative result of the public sector, private sector, and civil society. She asserts a new vision of the economy, one which confronts and addresses our contemporary grand challenges through collaboration and innovation—the mission-oriented approach. Using the case study of the Apollo programme, which directly contradicts the aforementioned myths and put a man on the moon almost 60 years ago, Mazzucato extracts six key attributes: 1. Vision and leadership with a sense of purpose; 2. Innovation through risk-taking and experimentation; 3. Organizational agility and flexibility (as opposed to governmental siloes); 4. Unpredictable and serendipitous spillover effects (a whole host of innovations from portable computers, wireless headsets, baby formula, camera phones, and home insulation were enabled by the Apollo programme); 5. Budgets based on outcomes and not costs; and 6. Partnership between the business and the government. She then looks to apply these learnings to some of current grand challenges of today, elaborating at some length on the application of the approach on the Sustainable Development Goals, the digital divide, and health and wellbeing. Mazzucato ends by proposing seven new principles to spur on the mission-oriented approach:
![]() Written by Nobel Laureate G. H. Hardy; a rare peek inside the mind of a genius mathematician. The Foreword by C.P. Snow is a superbly written portraiture of Hardy by a man who knew him intimately; I wondered how someone from the sciences could write so well; only after Wikipedia-ing him could I confirm my suspicions—Snow has also a double career as a writer and novelist. Snow’s Foreword provides the necessary somber tint to the Apology: “…[A Mathematician’s Apology] is also, in an understated stoical fashion, a passionate lament for creative powers that used to be and that will never come again… it is very rare for a writer to realize, with the finality of truth, that he is absolutely finished” (p. 51). Reading the book alongside the Foreword, we realize that the Apology is the work of a man reconsidering his life’s work after the childlike joy of creative ability has left him. As for the actual Apology itself, Hardy writes a rational justification for the pursuit of pure mathematics as a creative art, one capable of great beauty like poetry, although the association may feel alien to the contemporary mind. Where mathematics may differ is in its permanence: “The Greeks first spoke a language which modern mathematicians can understand… so Greek mathematics is ‘permanent’, more permanent even than Greek literature… ‘Immorality’ may be a silly word, but probably a mathematician has the best chance of whatever it may mean” (p. 81). (Although it must be noted that Bachelard in Poetics of Space writes something like “the metaphor [and perhaps poetry, by extension] is eternal”). Hardy provides a large number of insights into the field, valuable due to his stature and his life’s devotion to the field. In no particular order:
![]() If memory serves me correctly, in The Myth of Sisyphus, Albert Camus writes of Kafka as a writer of the absurd, which describes the unrelenting tension between human thirst for clarity in a silent, unresponsive, and Godless world. In The Castle, K. the land surveyor is called to the Castle to engage in land survey work—the land surveyor, one who imposes rational cartesian order?—almost 300 pages and five days later, K. makes no progress towards gaining admittance to the Castle. Throughout the five days, K plods along, stuck in restless snowfall, trapped in small dark homes and labyrinthine tunnels, mired in senseless bureaucratic procedures to which, he, as an outsider, finds incomprehensible, and meeting (and engaging in relations) with the town’s inhabitants, who follow the Castle’s absurd logic. To them, K the stranger is outside of their categorizations of the world, his fruitless journey is one that strives to earn bureaucratic and “categorical” recognition. Un-cultured and un-disciplined in their ways, he is dirt or matter out of place (Mary Douglas’ famous phrase in Purity and Danger)—his complete powerlessness is a source of generative power, of danger to the purity of their set categories. What is the Castle? Shrouded at times in fog and snow, perched upon a hill, the Castle is an undetermined signifier, at times a metaphor, an image, a symbol; never is it the case that the Castle is a castle is a castle. The Castle is the fountain from which the bureaucracy stems; however, it is foolish to reduce Kafka and the Castle to a libertarian nightmare and read it as a critique of the government as limiting individual freedoms. As in some of Kafka’s other works (e.g., The Trial, Before the Law), transgression against the bureaucracy is also a sin: there is a layering of religious and juridical meanings. The Barnabas family exemplifies these dual meanings: they were once well-to-do family that fell from grace and repute after the slightest mark of transgression in a dispute with a Castle official. Kafka never managed to complete The Castle, it is perhaps for this reason that, stylistically, The Castle is wordy and is full of paragraphs stretching dozens of pages—we are in a different territory from his taut and terse short stories, some of which are only a few sentences. (These short stories are potent: I watched a video of Judith Butler lecturing for 45 minutes on one two/three paragraph story.) The congested writing works for the purposes of the novel—as K. plods along, we, the readers plod along with him in Kafka’s dense writing. In the excellent introduction to the novel by Idris Parry, Parry writes that Kafka “understands the Fall as a present situation, our condition of self-awareness, not as an event which took place on a particular day in the remote past… ‘Only our concept of time,’ he says in one of his notes, ‘leads us to call the Last Judgement by that name. In fact, it’s a court in standing session.’ In other words, it’s taking place now, all the time” (p. xviii). Reading The Castle is like experiencing the Fall, the state of disintegration, the loss of harmony. Or perhaps it could be read as an exemplification of the secular, God-less state, if we return to Camus’ concept of the Absurd. With the death of God, there is no more hope for the redemptive power of transcendental meaning. The manuscript of The Castle ends mid-sentence: “She held a trembling hand out to K. and made him sit down beside her, she spoke with an effort, it was an effort to understand her, but what she said” (p. 297). Kafka’s unfinished manuscript denies any meaningful closure—it ends in the tritone—the readers are imprisoned without resolution just as K is trapped in ![]() Quite a landmark study in the literature that redirects the current narratives on automation into a new direction. I’m not sure how the “automation theorists” (as Benanav calls them) will respond to his study. I’m sure the academics will be forced to engage, while the consultants and pop theorists will continue to spew brand-market content (“research”). I begin with a brief summary of the automation discourse, although it has, in recent years, been widely propagated in the public sphere: technological developments are disrupting the labour market, displacing workers, and threaten to (or promise to, depending on ideological inclinations and positionality) automate a large portion of jobs. For some writers in the field, these technological developments are exponential (e.g., Kurzweil), promising vertiginous changes in the near future. The outcomes will disrupt the basic functioning of capitalism, leading to “a new form of life that does not organize itself around wage work and monetary exchange” (p. 7). Supported by data and rigorous scholarship, Benanav shows that the cause of job loss is the lack of growth in productivity, not the uncontrollable growth of productivity that is the result of technological development and automation. Benanav proposes a simple equation to capture the relationship between rates of employment growth, productivity growth, and output growth, which is true by definition: Δ output - Δ productivity = Δ employment, or the rate of growth of output minus the rate of growth of productivity equals the rate of growth of employment. In the narratives of automation theorists, the rise of labour productivity was responsible for negative rates of employment in the manufacturing sector, leading to de-industrialization; in fact, de-industrialization happened due to slowing rates of output beginning in 1973. De-industrialization began as a phenomenon in the Global North and soon spread throughout the world not because of technological growth, but because of worsening overcapacity. In the post-WWII era, the U.S. shared its technologies with countries like Germany and Japan, which pursue export-led national development, leading to overcapacity in the global market, and depressed prices worldwide. In this context, firms responded by globalizing production as more countries competed to enter into the global supply chain. In an interesting reversal, the countries that have suffered less from de-industrialization are those that have robotized more rather than less—high degrees of automation have led to competitive advantage in world markets, helping workers retain their jobs. The manufacturing sector is important due to the sector’s importance in the overall economy. Benanav shows that manufacturing output rates are closely related to the overall national GDP growth rates, given that “in terms of gross output—which unlike value added includes the costs of intermediate inputs (that is, the goods and services consumed by firms)—manufacturing’s “footprint” on the wider economy is significantly larger” (p. 35). The current sluggish growth in the global economy is due to the lack of another sector to replace the manufacturing sector (despite the hype around the ICT sector, I suppose). Overcapacity and decline of manufacturing output has led to a decline in levels of investment, and subsequently, a decline in demand for consumption and reduced levels of hiring. The historically low interest rates in the previous decade and a half have led mostly to financialization, stock buybacks, dividends etc., that characterize financialized capitalism. Due to the growing bubbles of financialized assets, Japanification is a looming threat. With this said, Benanav does acknowledge the potential of technology to affect the demand for labour, but low levels of investment and low costs of labour in a slow economic growth environment make technological automation a secondary cause, and not the primary one. Additionally, in the current ecosystem of technological development, firms incentivized by profit are unlikely to invest in full-automation technologies. Instead, leading tech companies are driven more by the logic of surveillance capitalism—“rather than focus on generating advances in artificial general intelligence, engineers at Facebook spend their time studying slot machines to figure out how to get people addicted to their website, so that they keep coming back to check for notifications, post content, and view advertisements” (p. 40). Theories of automation predict high unemployment rates. But instead of high unemployment rates, there is underemployment and precarity as a larger number of workers crowd into the service sector. The service sector exhibits different characteristics than the manufacturing sector, as there are lower rates of productivity growth and less opportunities for expansion. In fact, only by industrializing the sector has productivity increased, demonstrating the importance of the manufacturing sector once more. The service sector is a stagnant sector in the economy, reliant on the growth the overall economy. And without productivity growth, service sector workers are forced to accept suppressed wages to work, unless there is concerted political action to change the playing field. In light of his diagnosis of the under-demand for labour, which again, is due to industrial overcapacity, de-industrialization, and underinvestment, Benanav re-evaluates some of the popular policy proposals discussed in public discourse. Speaking on Keynesian policy proposals, he notes that, contrary to historical (common sense), “the era of counter-cyclical spending began in earnest in the 1970s” (p. 67); prior to this, the manufacturing sector in the post-war era was already characterized by strong labour demand. (An aside: it may be for this reason that Benanav holds an unorthodox view on financialization, particularly for someone on the left—it seems to me that in his view, financialization occurred due to the lack of productive investment opportunities, and not due to the neo-liberal turn.) He does return to Keynes and his discussion on economic maturity or the “secular stagnation,” in which “it would make more sense to intervene to shrink the labor supply rather than to stimulate labor demand, increasing leisure rather than output” (p. 69). However, this would require socialization of investment levels, as opposed to the current system where private investment can threaten a capital strike. The only way out of this conundrum would be through strong social movements, which is lacking in the current environment. Benanav is also skeptical of UBI as a policy proposal. In a low-growth environment, he fears that UBI will likely take on the right-wing variant that dismantles the remains of the welfare state without reorganizing production. With current environmental problems, one is unable to outgrow the problem of labour surplus—“only a conquest of production, which finally succeeds in wresting the power to control investment decision away from capitalists, hence rendering the capital strike inoperative, can clear the way for us to advance toward a post-scarcity future” (p. 79). In the final chapter, Benanav sketches out his vision of a post-scarcity world of co-operative production, where there are greater individual freedoms in the form of more free time for all. As he notes, “ for a post-scarcity society to come into being, a literal cornucopia is not required… abundance is a social relationship, based on the principle that the means of one’s existence will never be at stake in any of one’s relationships” (p. 89). Additional notes:
![]() Great study exploring micro-work and a new class of micro-workers, both of which have emerged from the needs of AI, mediated by crowdworking platforms. These new workers are the digital equivalents of the petty proletariat, doing all forms of precarious piecemeal work to sustain bare life. They bear the burden of stagnant economic growth, deindustrialization, and the neo-liberalization of the economy from the 1970s and the subsequent growth of subemployment and informal employment. While informal employment was the norm for the global South, it is now becoming the norm for the Global North as well, and with microwork sites, Jones writes that “platform capitalism brings both the logic and realities of informality to the very heart of accumulation as a new norm” (p. 29). Micro-workers are a necessity for the functioning of AI, but are obscured and ignored beneath the glitzy, hype-based, human-less promise of AI. AI and machine learning requires a large number of data labellers to make the data legible for AI algorithms and microwork platforms step in to redistribute the work to a growing army of precarious micro-workers. A vicious cycle governs this relationship—AI automates portions of jobs, leading to a growing number of micro-workers, who are involved in the further development of AI algorithms. In the process, good jobs turn into unregulated, informal, and badly paid work that is not bound by legal frameworks. The general consensus from neoliberal organizations like the World Bank frames micro-work as a developmental opportunity for the developing world—Jones’ account demonstrates that this is anything but the case. Wages are often unpaid or are gamified into tokens and rewards, long fallow periods of time are spent hunting for jobs rather than completing them, and after all of this, power asymmetries allow employers to withhold wages for workers. In some cases, unbanked workers are paid in gift cards, and “the platform comes to resemble a kind of digital company town” (p. 53). In this new labour arrangement, work undergoes a transformation: just as the artisanal craftsperson in the past turns into a commodified modern worker with limited contributions to the entire production process in the industrialized economy, with micro-work, modern professions “dissipate into a cloud of tasks” (p. 59). As this shift occurs, there is hyper-alienation of workers, “divesting workers of the capacity to know what they are doing and to what end” (p. 65). A troubling conclusion, given the use of microwork platforms by organizations like the Pentagon—some micro-workers in war-torn areas may be involved in the digging of their own figurative graves. Jones ends the book thinking about the form that labour struggle could adapt to in this new world, where there is “a capitalism without unions, worker culture and institutions” (p. 72) and fluid and geographically dispersed working arrangements (p. 84). To this end, he examines a wide variety of global wageless movements, blockades, and strikes that diverge in form, action, and demands from the unions of the past. ![]() Catherine Osborne’s very decent addition to the A Very Short Introduction series focusing on presocratic philosophy. The book briefly explores the key texts (or what is left of them—in the first chapter, Osborne discusses the incompleteness of these ancient texts and the process required to salvage them) and main ideas of a few of the major presocratic philosophers, like Empedocles, Parmenides, Zenos, and Pythagoras. Osborne orders the book alongside her contention with the general scholarship of presocratic philosophy. She criticizes the scholarship for forcing these various philosophers into conversation with one another. This makes for a neat and clean narrative about philosophical progression, but ends up obfuscating and sometimes, suppressing, elements of each philosophy. Osborne’s approach to the subject is to take each philosopher and their ideas in their own context. With this approach, Osborne exposes the readers to a wide variety of thinking among the presocratic philosophers, like Parmenides’ focus on being and becoming and appearance and truth, Zenos’ reality-questioning paradoxes, Heraclitus on identity and change, Pythagoras and his mysticism, and finally, the sophists. Osborne leaves us with a section for further reading materials for those that are interested in learning more about each philosopher. |
AuthorThis is a section for book reviews. I read all sorts of books and I read them in four languages. Archives
April 2023
Categories
All
|
Site powered by Weebly. Managed by Hostgator